Example: bachelor of science

Expected Utility Theory - Columbia University

Expected Utility TheoryMark DeanGR5211 - Microeconomic Analysis 1 Introduction Up until now, we have thought of subjects choosing betweenobjects Used cars Hamburgers Monetary amounts However, often the outcome of the choices that we make arenot known You are deciding whether or not to buy a share in AIG You are deciding whether or not to put your student loan onblack at the roulette table You are deciding whether or not to buy a house that straddlesthe San Andreas fault line In each case you understand what it is that you are choosingbetween, but you don t know the outcome of that choice In fact, many things can happen, you just don t know whichoneRisk vs Uncertainty We are going to di erentiate between two di erent ways inwhich the future may not be know Horse races Roulette wheels What is the di erence?Risk vs Uncertainty When playing a roulette wheel the probabilities areknown Everyone agrees on the likelihood of black So we (the researcher) can treat this as something we canobserve Probabilities are objective This is a situation ofriskRisk vs Uncertainty When betting on a horse race the probabilities areunknown Di erent people may apply di erent probabilities to a horsewinning We cannot directly observe a person s beliefs Probabilities are subjective This is a situation ofuncertainty (or ambiguity)Choices Under Risk So, how should yo

Bernoulli argued that people should be maximizing expected utility not expected value u( x) is the expected utility of an amount Moreover, marginal utility should be decreasing The value of an additional dollar gets lower the more money you have For example u($0) = 0 u($499,999) = 10 u($1,000,000) = 16

Tags:

  University, Lower, Expected, Columbia university, Columbia

Information

Domain:

Source:

Link to this page:

Please notify us if you found a problem with this document:

Other abuse

Transcription of Expected Utility Theory - Columbia University

1 Expected Utility TheoryMark DeanGR5211 - Microeconomic Analysis 1 Introduction Up until now, we have thought of subjects choosing betweenobjects Used cars Hamburgers Monetary amounts However, often the outcome of the choices that we make arenot known You are deciding whether or not to buy a share in AIG You are deciding whether or not to put your student loan onblack at the roulette table You are deciding whether or not to buy a house that straddlesthe San Andreas fault line In each case you understand what it is that you are choosingbetween, but you don t know the outcome of that choice In fact, many things can happen, you just don t know whichoneRisk vs Uncertainty We are going to di erentiate between two di erent ways inwhich the future may not be know Horse races Roulette wheels What is the di erence?Risk vs Uncertainty When playing a roulette wheel the probabilities areknown Everyone agrees on the likelihood of black So we (the researcher) can treat this as something we canobserve Probabilities are objective This is a situation ofriskRisk vs Uncertainty When betting on a horse race the probabilities areunknown Di erent people may apply di erent probabilities to a horsewinning We cannot directly observe a person s beliefs Probabilities are subjective This is a situation ofuncertainty (or ambiguity)Choices Under Risk So, how should you make choices under risk?

2 Let s consider the following (very boring) fairground game You ip a coin If it comes down heads you get $10 If it comes down tails you get $0 What is the maximum amountxthat you would pay in orderto play this game?Approach 1: Expected Value You have the following two options1 Not play the game and get $0 for sure2 Play the game and get $xwith probability 50% and$10 xwith probability 50% Approach 1: Expected value The Expected amount that you would earn from playing thegame ( x) + (10 x) This is bigger than 0 ( x) + (10 x) 05 x Should pay at most $5 to play the gameThe St. Petersburg Paradox This was basically the accepted approach until DanielBernoulli suggested the following modi cation of the game Flip a coin If it comes down heads you get $2 If tails, ip again If that coin comes down heads you get $4 If tails, ip again If that comes down heads, you get $8 Otherwise ip again and so on How much would you pay to play this game?

3 The St. Petersburg Paradox The Expected value is12$2+14$4+18$8+116$16+..=$1+$1+$1+$1+. .= So you should pay an in nite amount of money to play thisgame Which is why this is the St. PetersburgparadoxThe St. Petersburg Paradox So what is going wrong here? Consider the following example:ExampleSay a pauper nds a magic lottery ticket, that has a 50% chanceof $1 million and a 50% chance of nothing. A rich person o ers tobuy the ticket o him for $499,999 for sure. According to our Expected value method , the pauper should refuse the richperson s o er!The St. Petersburg Paradox It seems ridiculous (and irrational) that the pauper wouldreject the o er Why? Because the di erence in life outcomes between $0 and$499,999 is massive Get to eat, buy clothes, etc Whereas the di erence between $499,999 and $1,000,000 isrelatively small A third pair of silk pyjamas Thus, by keeping the lottery, the pauper risks losing an awfullot ($0 vs $499,999) against gaining relatively little ($499,999vs $1,000,000)Marginal Utility Bernoulli argued that people should be maximizing expectedutilitynot expectedvalue u(x)is the Expected Utility of an amountx Moreover, marginal Utility should bedecreasing The value of an additional dollar gets lower the more moneyyou have For exampleu($0) =0u($499,999) =10u($1,000,000) =16 Marginal Utility Under this scheme, the pauper should choose the rich person so er as long as12u($1,000,000) +12u($0)<u($499,999)

4 Using the numbers on the previous slide, LHS=8, RHS=10 Pauper should accept the rich persons o er Bernoulli suggestedu(x) =ln(x) Also explains the St. Petersberg paradox Using this Utility function, should pay about $64 to play thegameRisk Aversion Notice that if people Maximize Expected Utility Have decreasing marginal Utility ( Utility is concave) They will berisk averse Will always reject a lottery in favor of receiving its expectedvalue for sureRisk AversionExpected Utility Expected Utility Theory is the workhorse model of choiceunder risk Unfortunately, it is another model which has somethingunobservable The Utility of every possible outcome of a lottery So we have to gure out how to test it We have already gone through this process for the model of standard ( not Expected ) Utility maximization Is this enough for Expected Utility maximization?Data In order to answer this question we need to state what ourdata is We are going to take as our primitve preferences Not choices But we know how to go from choices to preferences, yes?

5 But preferences over what? In the beginning we had preferences over objects For temptation and self control we used menus Now lotteries !Lotteries What is a lottery? Like any lottery ticket, it gives you a probability of winning anumber of prizes Let s imagine there are four possible prizes a(pple),b(anana),c(elery),d(ragonfruit) Then a lottery is just a probability distribution over This is a lottery that gives 15% chance of winninga, 35%chance of winningb, 50% of winningcand 0% chance ofwinningdLotteries More generally, a lottery is anyp=0BB@papbpcpd1 CCA Such that px 0 xpx=1De nitionLetXbe some nite prize space, The set (X)of lotteries onXisthe set of all functionsp:X![0,1]such that x2Xp(x) =1 Expected Utility We say that preferences have anexpected utilityrepresentationif we can Find utilities onprizes (a),u(b),u(c),u(d) Such thatp qif and only ifpau(a) +pbu(b) +pcu(c) +pdu(d)>qau(a) +qbu(b) +qcu(c) +qdu(d) xpxu(x) xqxu(x) Expected UtilityDe nitionA preference relation on lotteries on some nite prize spaceXhave an Expected Utility representation if there exists a functionu:X!

6 Rsuch thatp qif and only if x2Xp(x)u(x) x2Xq(x)u(x) Notice that preferences are on (X)but Utility numbers areonXExpected Utility What needs to be true about preferences for us to be able to nd an Expected Utility representation? Hint: you know a partial answer to this Anexpected utilityrepresentation is still autilityrepresentation So preferences must be Complete Transitive Re exiveExpected Utility Unsurprisingly, this is not enough We need two further axioms1 The Independence Axiom2 The Archimedian AxiomThe Independence AxiomQuestion: Think of two di erent lotteries, forconcreteness, let s say thatpis a 25% chance ofwinning the apple and a 75% chance of winning thebanana, whileqis a 75% chance of winning theapple and a 25% chance of winning the banana. Sayyou prefer the lotterypto the lotteryq. Now I o eryou the following choice between option 1 and 21I ip a coin. If it comes up heads, then you getp.

7 Otherwise you get the lottery that gives youthe celery for sure2I ip a coin. If it comes up heads, you you get the lottery that gives you thecelery for sureWhich do you prefer?The Independence Axiom The independence axiom says that if you must preferptoqyou must prefer option 1 to option 2 If I preferptoq, I must prefer a mixture ofpwith anotherlottery toqwith another lotteryThe Independence Axiom Say a consumer prefers lotteryptolotteryq. Then, for any other lotteryrand number0< 1 they must prefer p+ (1 )rto q+ (1 )r Notice that, while the independence axiom may seem intutive,that is dependent on the setting Maybe you prefer ice cream to gravy, but you don t prefer icecream mixed with steak to gravy mixed with steakThe Archimedean Axiom The other axiom we need is more techincal It basically says that no lottery is in nitely good or in nitelybadThe Archimedean Axiom For all lotteriesp,qandrsuch thatp q r, there must exist anaandbin(0,1)suchthatap+ (1 a)r q bp+ (1 b)rThe Expected Utility Theorem It turns out that these two axioms, when added to the standard ones, are necessary and su cient for an expectedutility representationTheoremLet X be a nite set of prizes , (X)be the set of lotteries on be a binary relation on (X).

8 Then is complete,re exive, transitive and satis es the Independence andArchimedean axioms if and only if there exists a u:X!Rsuchthat, for any p,q2 (X),p qif and only if x2 Xpxu(x) x2 Xqxu(x)The Expected Utility Theorem Proof? Do you want us to go through the proof? Oh, alright then Actually, Necessity is easy You will do it for homework Su ciency is harder Will sketch it hereProof Key to the proof is the following lemmaLemma If is complete, re exive, transitive and satis es theIndependence and Archimedean axioms then1p qand 0 < 1 implies p+ (1 )q p+ (1 )q2p q randp rimplies that there exists aunique such thatq p+ (1 )r The Expected Utility Theorem Step 1 Find the best prize - in other words the prize such that gettingthat prize for sure is preferred to all other lotteries. Give thatprize Utility 1 (for convenience, let s say thatais the best prize) Step 2 Find the worst prize - in other words the prize such that alllotteries are preferred to getting that prize for sure.

9 Give thatprize Utility 0 (for convenience, let s say thatdis the worseprize) Step 3 Show that, ifa>b, thena a+ (1 a) d b a+ (1 b) dwhere xis the lottery that gives prizexfor sure (this isintuitively obvious, but needs to be proved from theindependence axiom)The Expected Utility Theorem Step 4 For other prizes ( ), nd the probability such that theconsumer is indi erent between getting apples with probability and dragonfruit with probability(1 ), and bananas forsure. Letu(b) = . @01001 CCA u(b)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 u(b))0BB@00011 CCA(for us to know such a exists requires the Archimedeanaxiom) Step 5 Do the same forc, so0BB@00101 CCA u(c)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 u(c))0BB@00011 CCAThe Expected Utility Theorem So now we have found Utility numbers for every prize All we have to do is show thatp qif and only if x2 Xpxu(x) x2 Xqxu(x) Let s do a simple Expected Utility Theorem First, notice @00101 CCA ButThe Expected Utility Theorem But0BB@01001 CCA u(b)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 u(b))0BB@00011 CCAand0BB@00101 CCA u(c)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 u(c))0BB@00011 CCAThe Expected Utility Theoremp @u(b)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 @u(c)0BB@10001 CCA+ (1 u(c))0BB@00011 CCA1 CCAThe Expected Utility Theorem=( (b) + (c))0BB@10001 CCA+(1 (b) (c))0BB@00011 CCAThe Expected Utility Theorem Sopis indi erent to a lottery that puts probability( (b) + (c))on the best prize (and the remainder on the worst prize))

10 But this is just the Expected Utility ofp Similarlyqis ind erent to a lottery that puts( (b) + (c))on the best prize But this is just the Expected Utility ofqThe Expected Utility Theorem Sopwill be preferred toqif the Expected Utility ofpis higherthan the Expected Utility ofq This is because this means thatpis indi erent to a lotterywhich puts a higher weight on the best prize than doesq QED (ish) Expected Utility Numbers Remember that when we talked about standard utilitytheory, the numbers themselves didn t mean very much Only the order mattered So, for exampleu(a) =1v(a) =1u(b) =2v(b) =4u(c) =3v(c) =9u(d) =4v(c) =16 Would represent the same preferencesExpected Utility Numbers Is the same true here? No! According to the rst preferences12u(a) +12u(c) =2=u(b)and so12a+12c b But according to the second set of utilities12v(a) +12v(c) =5>v(b)and so12a+12c bExpected Utility Numbers So we have to take Utility numbers more seriously here Magnitudes matter How much more seriously?


Related search queries