Example: bankruptcy

HOMO SACER Sovereign Power and Bare Life …

homo SACER . Sovereign Power and Bare Life Giorgio Agamben homo SACER . Sovereign Power and Bare Life was originally published as homo SACER . Il potere sovrano e la nuda vita, 1995 Giulio Einaudi editore Contents Introduction 4. PART ONE: THE LOGIC OF SOVEREIGNTY. 1 The Paradox of Sovereignty 12. 2 'Nomos Basileus' 22. 3 Potentiality and Law 28. 4 Form of Law 35. Threshold 44. PART TWO: homo SACER . 1 homo SACER 47. 2 The Ambivalence of the Sacred 50. 3 Sacred Life 54. 4 'Vitae Necisque Potestas' 58. 5 Sovereign Body and Sacred Body 61.

HOMO SACER Sovereign Power and Bare Life Introduction The Greeks had no single term to express what we mean by the word "life." They used two terms that, although traceable to a common etymological root,

Tags:

  Power, Sovereign, Homo, Bear, Cesar, Homo sacer sovereign power and bare

Information

Domain:

Source:

Link to this page:

Please notify us if you found a problem with this document:

Other abuse

Transcription of HOMO SACER Sovereign Power and Bare Life …

1 homo SACER . Sovereign Power and Bare Life Giorgio Agamben homo SACER . Sovereign Power and Bare Life was originally published as homo SACER . Il potere sovrano e la nuda vita, 1995 Giulio Einaudi editore Contents Introduction 4. PART ONE: THE LOGIC OF SOVEREIGNTY. 1 The Paradox of Sovereignty 12. 2 'Nomos Basileus' 22. 3 Potentiality and Law 28. 4 Form of Law 35. Threshold 44. PART TWO: homo SACER . 1 homo SACER 47. 2 The Ambivalence of the Sacred 50. 3 Sacred Life 54. 4 'Vitae Necisque Potestas' 58. 5 Sovereign Body and Sacred Body 61.

2 6 The Ban and the Wolf 69. Threshold 74. 1. PART THREE: THE CAMP AS BIOPOLITICAL. PARADIGM OF THE MODERN. 1 The Politicization of Life 76. 2 Biopolitics and the Rights of Man 81. 3 Life That Does Not Deserve to Live 87. 4 'Politics, or Giving Form to the Life of a People' 92. 5 VP 99. 6 Politicizing Death 103. 7 The Camp as the 'Nomos' of the Modern 107. Threshold 117. Bibliography 122. 2. Das Recht hat kein Dasein f r sich, sein Wesen vielmehr ist das Leben der Menschen selbst, von einer Seite angesehen. -- Savigny Law has no existence for itself; rather its essence lies, from a certain perspective, in the very life of men.

3 Ita in iure civitatis, civiumque officiis investigandis opus est, non quidern ut dissolvatur civitas, sed tamen ut tanquam dissoluta consideretur, id est, ut qualis sit natura humana, quibus rebus ad civitatem compaginandam apta vel inepta sit, et quomodo homines inter se componi debeant, qui coalescere volunt, recte intelligatur. -- Hobbes To make a more curious search into the rights of States, and duties of Subjects, it is necessary, (I say not to take them in sunder, but yet that) they be so considered, as if they were dissolved, ( ) that wee rightly understand what the quality of humane nature is, in what matters it is, in what not fit to make up a civill government, and how men must be agreed among themselves, that intend to grow up into a well-grounded State.

4 Euret moi h entol h eis z n, aut eis thanaton. -- Saint Paul And the commandment, which was ordained to life, I found to be unto death. 3. homo SACER . Sovereign Power and Bare Life Introduction The Greeks had no single term to express what we mean by the word "life.". They used two terms that, although traceable to a common etymological root, are semantically and morphologically distinct: zo , which expressed the simple fact of living common to all living beings (animals, men, or gods), and bios, which indicated the form or way of living proper to an individual or a group.

5 When Plato mentions three kinds of life in the Philebus, and when Aristotle distinguishes the contemplative life of the philosopher (bios the r tikos) from the life of pleasure (bios apolaustikos) and the political life (bios politikos) in the Nichomachean Ethics, neither philosopher would ever have used the term zo (which in Greek, significantly enough, lacks a plural). This follows from the simple fact that what was at issue for both thinkers was not at all simple natural life but rather a qualified life, a particular way of life.

6 Concerning God, Aristotle can certainly speak of a zo arist kai aidios, a more noble and eternal life ( Metaphysics, 1072b, 28), but only insofar as he means to underline the significant truth that even God is a living being (similarly, Aristotle uses the term zo in the same context -- and in a way that is just as meaningful -- to define the act of thinking). But to speak of a zo . politik of the citizens of Athens would have made no sense. Not that the classical world had no familiarity with the idea that natural life, simple zo as such, could be a good in itself.

7 In a passage of the Politics, after noting that the end of the city is life according to the good, Aristotle expresses his awareness of that idea with the most perfect lucidity: This [life according to the good] is the greatest end both in common for all men and for each man separately. But men also come together and maintain the political community in view of simple living, because there is probably some kind of good in the mere fact of living itself [kata to z n auto monon]. If there is no great difficulty as to the way of life [kata ton bion], clearly most men will tolerate much suffering and hold on to life [zo ] as if it were a kind of serenity [eu meria, beautiful day] and a natural sweetness.

8 ( 1278b, 23-31). In the classical world, however, simple natural life is excluded from the polis in the strict sense, and remains confined -- as merely reproductive life -- to the sphere of the oikos, "home" ( Politics, 1252a, 26-35). At the beginning of the Politics, Aristotle takes the greatest care to distinguish the oikonomos (the head of an estate) and the despotts (the head of the family), both of whom are concerned with the reproduction and the subsistence of life, from the politician, and he scorns those who think the difference between the two is one of quantity and not of kind.

9 And when Aristotle defined the end of the perfect community in a passage that was to become canonical for the political tradition of the West ( 1252b, 30), he did so precisely by opposing the simple fact of living (to z n) to politically qualified life (to eu z n): ginomen men oun tou z n heneken, ousa de tou eu z n, "born with regard to life, but existing essentially with regard to the good life" (in the Latin translation of William of 4. Moerbeke, which both Aquinas and Marsilius of Padua had before them: facta quidem igitur vivendi gratia, existens autem gratia bene vivendi).

10 It is true that in a famous passage of the same work, Aristotle defines man as a politikon z on ( Politics, 1253a, 4). But here (aside from the fact that in Attic Greek the verb bionai is practically never used in the present tense), "political". is not an attribute of the living being as such, but rather a specific difference that determines the genus z on. (Only a little later, after all, human politics is distinguished from that of other living beings in that it is founded, through a supplement of politicity [policit ] tied to language, on a community not simply of the pleasant and the painful but of the good and the evil and of the just and the unjust.)


Related search queries